ResearchGate D-4508-2014
- International Association for Promoting Geoethics (IAPG)
- Ronin Research Scholar @edgeryders; Member of EGU, AGU
- recent publication: Geo-societal Narratives - Contextualising Geosciences
Recent research into the societal context of geosciences led modern geo-philosophical frameworks to guide professionals and citizens when interacting with World and Planet Earth. These frameworks combine insights into societal and geoscientific features of the World and Earth into a joint knowledge system (Bohle et al., 2020). Hence, how they are constructed is paramount.
Introduction
Geo-philosophical frameworks are epistemic problems at the borderline of different knowledge domains (Renn, 2020). Generally, these frameworks often are tacit about their philosophical foundations, exceptions apart (Frodeman, 2003; Marone and Bohle, 2020). This silence is disadvantageous because the particular philosophical foundation determines how societal practices are understood when shaping the Human-Earth Nexus, the bundle of planet Earth, a planetary technosphere, and a hegemonic culture (Haff, 2014; Lemmens et al., 2017; Rosol et al., 2017; Dyer-Witheford, 2018; Dryzek and Pickering, 2019).
Various modern geo-philosophical frameworks inspect the Human-Earth Nexus; see, for example (Zen, 1993; Peppoloni and Di Capua, 2012; Frodeman, 2014; Cherkashin and Sklyanova, 2016; Nikitina, 2016; Di Capua et al., 2017; Bohle, 2020). These frameworks differ by an epistemic foundation in modern Earth System Literacy from earlier frameworks like noosphere (Vernadsky, 1945; Oldfield and Shaw, 2006; Korobova and Romanov, 2014) or Gaia (Lovelock J., 1979; Lovelock, 1990; Lenton and Van Oijen, 2002; Onori and Visconti, 2012).
The modern geo-philosophical frameworks apply, at least implicitly, realist-materialist epistemologies to understand geoscientific features (Bunge, 2006; Marone et al., 2019). Other epistemological concepts for geo-philosophical frameworks like hermeneutic phenomenology exist (Raab and Frodeman, 2002; Frodeman, 2014). Hence, geo-philosophical frameworks are distinguished by their epistemic foundation and the specific philosophical foundations, which refer to insights into societal features and normative settings.
Example: Cape Town Geoethics
The following illustrative description looks into the school of geo-philosophical frameworks called ‘geoethics’ because the author is familiar with it. The analysis starts with a variant of geoethics, which was summarised in the Cape Town Statement on Geoethics (Di Capua et al., 2017) at the occasion of the 35th International Geological Congress and detailed in 2019 (Peppoloni et al., 2019); hence, for the following, this variant is called ‘Cape Town Geoethics’.
Among the notions that label modern geo-philosophical frameworks, geoethics stands out, despite the term having different connotations (Bohle and Marone, 2021b). As an emergent moral philosophy, geoethics was defined (Peppoloni and Di Capua, 2015b; p.4) as “research and reflection on the values which underpin appropriate behaviours and practices, wherever human activities interact with the Earth system”. Summarising the state-of-the-art of this school of thought, Peppoloni et al. (2019) describe Cape Town Geoethics as an aspirational virtue-ethics for the individual human agent acting at the Human-Earth Nexus. Potthast (2021) defines geoethics as an epistemic-moral hybrid, and Peppoloni and Di Capua (2021a; p. 20) qualify an updated variant of Cape Town Geoethics as a “modern virtue-ethics”. The Cape Town Geoethics and later variants are founded on (implicit) Kantian moral philosophies (Marone and Bohle, 2020).
Emerging within geology (Lambert, 2012), geoethics was an intra-disciplinary endeavour (Peppoloni, 2012a, 2012b; Peppoloni and Di Capua, 2015a, 2015b) striving for responsible geosciences (Manduca and Mogk, 2006; Mogk, 2018). Although neighbouring fields such as environmental ethics (Yannacone, 1999; Martínez-Frías, 2008; Hourdequin, 2015), similar constructs in geosciences (Frodeman, 2003) and other disciplines (Forbes and Lindquist, 2000; Lynn, 2000; Cutchin, 2002; Kirby and Houle, 2004; Jennings et al., 2009), and open issues (Bohle and Di Capua, 2019) are known, these sources like general studies in ethics (see for example (Callahan and Engelhardt, 1981; Shearman, 1990; Han, 2015)) were not much explored.
Although the vastness of fields related to geoethics may be frightening, likely significant contributions are missed when staying ‘parochial’, as illustrated by the following example. As designed from the onset (Peppoloni and Di Capua, 2012), Cape Town Geoethics should enable ethically sound operational practices of geoscientists depending on environmental, social and cultural settings. Hence, geoethical practices aim at comparative Justice and pluralism of sound choices. This idea of Justice is well-established (Sen, 2010), of which, however, those who pursue developing geoethics (the author included) have not been adequately and early aware.
Such experience of parochial
circumstances motivated some authors to seek interdisciplinary exposure and
study the philosophical foundations of Cape Town (Bohle et al., 2019; Marone and Marone, 2019; Marone
and Bohle, 2020; Bohle and Marone, 2021a). In due course of study, it
became apparent that Cape Town Geoethics has a compound design and shows conceptual
discontinuities. For example, insights
into the functioning of the Earth System (Earth Science Literacy) are gained by
implementing realist-materialist philosophies. However, the geoethical practice of
comparative Justice is founded on aspirational norms, which implement subjectivist-idealist
moral philosophies. Consequently, the geo-philosophical
framework underpinning Cape Town Geoethics is hybrid, and it is exceeding the realm
of a realist-materialist scientific epistemology (Bunge, 2006).
Several valuable features characterise Cape Town Geoethics, its predecessors and variants, which, however, may need examination:
- First, the autonomy of the human agent is the pivotal tenet of any variant of Cape Town Geoethics, most explicit for the variant envisioning ecological humanism (Peppoloni and Di Capua, 2020; p.17). The concept of autonomy of the human agent encapsulates the moral core of geoethics, applying a subjectivist-idealist philosophy for normative settings. However, human autonomy is limited in any societal reality. Human autonomy is contextual and not ‘categorial’ (e.g. Kantian; see (Marone and Bohle, 2020)). For example, differentials of power, voice, sense-making skills, group pressure or access to resources (knowledge included) limit human autonomy. Thus, free will or free agency would be bounded, if not precluded. Therefore, this pivotal tenet of the geo-philosophical framework ‘geoethics’ needs deeper examination.
- Second, diverging practices emerge when responsible and ethically sound choices depend on environmental, social and cultural settings, which are given. Such ‘operational pluralism’ or ‘functional plasticity’ is a central design feature of geoethics, acknowledging, for example for Cape Town Geoethics, that choices “taken in a specific social and cultural setting, that respect the ethical norms of this setting, may appear unethical elsewhere” (Peppoloni et al., 2019; p.30). This feature is essential to handle the diversity of circumstances at the Human-Earth Nexus, and therefore, it should be kept while also acknowledging the partial autonomy of human agents.
- Third, comparative Justice and operational pluralism are essential in any geo-philosophical framework for agents acting at the Human-Earth Nexus. However, it exposes the human agent to high decision-loads and requires adjusting messages to audiences and circumstances. Under these complex conditions (see (Sen, 2010)), aspirational norms give only limited guidance because these norms are categorical and independent of the agent, circumstance and audience. For example, the acclamations of the Geoethical Promise (Matteucci et al., 2014), such as “I will never misuse my geoscience knowledge, resisting constraint or coercion”, are praiseworthy. However, the question arises, how they can be applied given challenging circumstances of partial autonomy of human agents?
Conclusion
None of the current variants of
geoethics (Cape Town Geoethics, its predecessors and variants) examined the
impact of the limited autonomy (also understood as limited free agency) of
human agents and related features. This lacuna should be addressed
within the general operational structure of the Cape Town Geoethics. Methodologically it could be done by
enlarging its foundations with specific political and moral philosophies, which
apply a realist-materialist scientific
epistemology (Bunge, 2006) to understand the societal fabric.
Bohle, M. (2020). Geo-Societal Sense-Making. Geol. Soc. London, Spec.
Publ., SP508-2019–213. doi:10.1144/SP508-2019-213.
Bohle, M., and Di Capua, G. (2019). ‘Setting the Scene’, in Exploring
Geoethics, ed. M. Bohle (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 1–24.
doi:10.1007/978-3-030-12010-8_1.
Bohle, M., and Marone, E. (2021a). Geo-societal Narratives -
Contextualising Geosciences. , eds. M. Bohle and E. Marone Cham: Springer
International Publishing doi:10.1007/978-3-030-79028-8.
Bohle, M., and Marone, E. (2021b). Geoethics, a Branding for Sustainable
Practices. Sustainability 13, 895. doi:10.3390/su13020895.
Bohle, M., Nauen, C. E., and Marone, E. (2019). Ethics to Intersect Civic
Participation and Formal Guidance. Sustainability 11, 773.
doi:10.3390/su11030773.
Bohle, M., Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2020). Viewing Earth and World
through the geoethical lens. Hum. Futur., 28–29.
Bunge, M. A. (1989). Treaties on Basic Philosophy -Ethics: The Good and
The Right. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Bunge, M. A. (2006). Chasing Reality. Toronto St. Toronto:
University of Toronto Press doi:10.3138/9781442672857.
Callahan, D., and Engelhardt, H. T. (1981). The Roots of Ethics. ,
eds. D. Callahan and H. T. Engelhardt Boston, MA: Springer US
doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-3303-6.
Cherkashin, A. K., and Sklyanova, I. P. (2016). The manifestation of the
principles of geoecological ethics: Environmental approach. Geogr. Nat.
Resour. 37, 271–280. doi:10.1134/S1875372816030112.
Cutchin, M. P. (2002). Ethics and geography: continuity and emerging
syntheses. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 26, 656–664. doi:10.1191/0309132502ph393pr.
Di Capua, G., Peppoloni, S., and Bobrowsky, P. (2017). The Cape Town
Statement on Geoethics. Ann. Geophys. 60, 1–6. doi:10.4401/ag-7553.
Dryzek, J. S., and Pickering, J. (2019). The politics of the
Anthropocene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dyer-Witheford, N. (2018). ‘Struggles in the Planet Factory: Class
Composition and Global Warming’, in Interrogating the Anthropocene
(Cham: Springer International Publishing), 75–103.
doi:10.1007/978-3-319-78747-3_2.
Forbes, W., and Lindquist, C. (2000). Philosophical, Professional, and
Environmental Ethics An Overview for Foresters. J. For. 98, 4–10.
Frodeman, R. (2003). Geo-Logic: Breaking Ground Between Philosophy and
the Earth Sciences. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Frodeman, R. (2014). ‘Hermeneutics in the Field: The Philosophy of Geology’,
in The Multidimensionality of Hermeneutic Phenomenology. Contributions to
Phenomenology, eds. B. Babich and D. Ginev (Cham: Springer), 69–79.
doi:10.1007/978-3-319-01707-5_5.
Haff, P. K. (2014). Humans and technology in the Anthropocene: Six rules. Anthr.
Rev. 1, 126–136. doi:10.1177/2053019614530575.
Han, H. (2015). Virtue Ethics, Positive Psychology, and a New Model of
Science and Engineering Ethics Education. Sci. Eng. Ethics 21, 441–460.
doi:10.1007/s11948-014-9539-7.
Hourdequin, M. (2015). Environmental Ethics - from Theory to Practice.
London, UK: Bloomsbury Publishing Ülc.
Jennings, B., Heltne, P., and Kintzelle, K. (2009). Principles of Water
Ethics. Minding Nat., 25–28.
Jonas, H. (1984). The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of Ethics
for the Technological Age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kirby, K., and Houle, F. A. (2004). Ethics and the Welfare of the Physics
Profession. Phys. Today 57, 42–46. doi:10.1063/1.1839376.
Kohlberg, L. (1981). The Philosophy of Moral Development: Moral Stages
and the Idea of Justice. San Francisco: Harber & Row.
Korobova, E., and Romanov, S. (2014). Ecogeochemical exploration of
noosphere in light of ideas of V.I. Vernadsky. J. Geochemical Explor.
147, 58–64. doi:10.1016/j.gexplo.2014.01.024.
Lambert, I. B. (2012). Geoethics: a perspective from Australia. Ann.
Geophys. 55. doi:10.4401/ag-5556.
Lemmens, P., Blok, V., and Zwier, J. (2017). Toward a Terrestrial Turn in
Philosophy of Technology. Techné Res. Philos. Technol. 21, 114–126.
doi:10.5840/techne2017212/363.
Lenton, T. M., and Van Oijen, M. (2002). Gaia as a complex adaptive
system. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.1014.
Lovelock J. (1979). Gaia. A New Look at Life on Earth. Oxford
University Press.
Lovelock, J. E. (1990). Hands up for the Gaia hypothesis. Nature
344, 100–102. doi:10.1038/344100a0.
Lynn, W. S. (2000). Geoethics: Ethics, Geography and Moral Understanding.
Manduca, C. A., and Mogk, D. W. (2006). Earth and Mind: How Geologists
Think and Learn about the Earth. Boulder, Colorado: Geological Society of
America doi:10.1130/SPE413.
Marone, E., and Bohle, M. (2020). Geoethics for Nudging Human Practices in
Times of Pandemics. Sustainability 12, 7271. doi:10.3390/su12187271.
Marone, E., and Marone, L. (2019). ‘Ethical Dimensions of Ocean Governance’,
in The Future of Ocean Governance and Capacity Development, eds. D.
Werle, P. R. Boudreau, M. R. Brooks, M. J. A. Butler, A. Charles, S.
Coffen-Smout, et al. (Brill | Nijhoff), 34–39. doi:10.1163/9789004380271_008.
Marone, L., Lopez de Casenave, J., and González del Solar, R. (2019). The
synthetic thesis of truth helps mitigate the “reproducibility crisis” and is an
inspiration for predictive ecology. Humanit. J. Valparaiso, 363–376.
doi:10.22370/rhv2019iss14pp363-376.
Martínez-Frías, J. (2008). Geoethics: Proposal of a geosciences-oriented
formal definition and future planetary perspectives. 1. Available at:
http://tierra.rediris.es/documentos/Geoethics_Tierra_Network_2008.pdf.
Matteucci, R., Gosso, G., Peppoloni, S., Piacente, S., Wasowski, J.,
Matteucci, R., et al. (2014). The “ Geoethical Promise ”: A Proposal. Ital.
Fed. Earth Sci. 37, 190–191.
Mogk, D. (2018). Geoethics and Professionalism: The Responsible Conduct of
Scientists. Ann. Geophys. 60. doi:10.4401/AG-7584.
Nikitina, N. (2016). Geoethics: Theory, Principles, Problems.
Geoinformmark Ltd. Moscow.
Oldfield, J. D., and Shaw, D. J. B. (2006). V.I. Vernadsky and the
noosphere concept: Russian understandings of society–nature interaction. Geoforum
37, 145–154. doi:10.1016/j.geoforum.2005.01.004.
Onori, L., and Visconti, G. (2012). The GAIA theory: From Lovelock to
Margulis. from a homeostatic to a cognitive autopoietic worldview. Rend.
Lincei 23. doi:10.1007/s12210-012-0187-z.
Peppoloni, S. (2012a). Ethical and cultural value of the Earth sciences.
Interview with Prof. Giulio Giorello. Ann. Geophys. 55.
doi:10.4401/ag-5755.
Peppoloni, S. (2012b). Social aspects of the Earth sciences Interview with
Prof . Franco Ferrarotti. doi:10.4401/ag-5632.
Peppoloni, S., Bilham, N., and Di Capua, G. (2019). ‘Contemporary
Geoethics Within the Geosciences’, in Exploring Geoethics (Cham:
Springer International Publishing), 25–70. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-12010-8_2.
Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2012). Geoethics and geological culture:
Awareness, responsibility and challenges. Ann. Geophys. 55, 335–341.
doi:10.4401/ag-6099.
Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2015a). Geoethics, the role and
responsibility of geoscientists. Lyell Coll. , ed. Peppoloni S. and Di
Capua G. London: Geological Society of London doi:10.1144/SP419.0.
Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2015b). ‘The Meaning of Geoethics’, in Geoethics,
ed. Wyss M. and Peppoloni S. (Elsevier), 3–14.
doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-799935-7.00001-0.
Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2020). Geoethics as global ethics to face
grand challenges for humanity. Geol. Soc. London, Spec. Publ.,
SP508-2020–146. doi:10.1144/SP508-2020-146.
Peppoloni, S., and Di Capua, G. (2021). ‘Current Definition and Vision of
Geoethics’, in Geo-societal Narratives (Cham: Springer International
Publishing), 17–28. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-79028-8_2.
Potthast, T. (2021). ‘Geosciences and Geoethics in Transition: Research
Perspectives from Ethics and Philosophy of Science—A Commentary’, in Geo-societal
Narratives (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 213–216. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-79028-8_16.
Raab, T., and Frodeman, R. (2002). What is it like to be a geologist? A
phenomenology of geology and its epistemological implications. Philos.
Geogr. doi:10.1088/0022-3719/14/26/011.
Renn, J. (2020). The Evolution of Knowledge - Rethinking Science for
the Anthropocene. Oxford, UK: Princeton University Press.
Rosol, C., Nelson, S., and Renn, J. (2017). Introduction: In the machine
room of the Anthropocene. Anthr. Rev. 4, 2–8.
doi:10.1177/2053019617701165.
Sen, A. (2010). The idea of Justice. London, UK: Penguin Books.
Shearman, R. (1990). The meaning and ethics of sustainability. Environ.
Manage. 14, 1–8. doi:10.1007/BF02394014.
Vernadsky, W. I. (1945). The Biosphere and the Noösphere. Am. Sci.
33, 1–12.
Yannacone, V. J. (1999). Science, Ethics, and Scientific Ethics in the
Modern World. Environ. Geosci. 6, 164–171.
doi:10.1046/j.1526-0984.1999.64002.x.
Zen, E.-A. (1993). The Citizen-Geologist. GSA Today 3, 2–3.
No comments:
Post a Comment